Skip to main content

How (Philosophically) Deep Is Your Love?: A Thomistic Analysis of Romantic Love



           There’s a line in St. Augustine’s Confessions that (even though I haven’t read it in full) had stuck to me ever since I read it as a seventeen-year-old: “Pondus meum amor meus ; eo feror, quocunque feror”, or, in English: “My weight is my love, it takes me wherever I go.”[i]
          This is indeed very true upon self-reflection. Love draws us to whatever it is we love. It pulls us to our beloved. As Dr. Peter Kreeft puts it, “love is our spiritual gravity, our mass, our density – and our destiny”[ii]. Our love for food draws us to it at times of hunger, we want to run to our beloved friends every time we feel miserable, we might resort to our love for wine to numb ourselves a little bit during moments of stress, or we might to turn to the God of Love when we are spiritually lost. Love indeed moves us away from ourselves to unite ourselves to another. Love takes us from the mere “I” and puts us to the “we”: “I and my favorite food”, Me and my friends”, “The Lord and I”.
          But there’s a very special kind of love that captivates us in a very different way than mere love for food or friend. It’s a love that I don’t think escapes the common man. We’ve all felt it, I believe, and we’ve been ecstatic, excited, flattered, or even hurt because of it. It’s called romance. And for a lot of people, this love knocks on their hearts often, and it scares them: it might end up in heartbreak (again!).
          The purpose of this essay is to ask this question: what, precisely, is romantic love? Specifically, what is romance in the Thomistic perspective (in the philosophical/theological study of St Thomas Aquinas’ thought)? In order to answer this question, it is important to know what love is in general first. So, let us, first and foremost, inquire: what is love?

Defining the building blocks of Romance

          Aquinas, in the Summa Theologiae, uses the word “love” in three different ways: it may refer to the Love of God (Prima Pars, Question 20) which, since He is ontologically simple, is Himself, that is why “God is Love” (1 John 4:8). It may also refer to the supernatural virtue of love, or Charity (Secunda Secundae Partis, Questions 23-46), the same love that St. Paul speaks of in 1 Corinthians 13. Lastly, it may refer to the passion, or the emotion, of love (Prima Secundae Partis, Question 26). This is the kind of love that Aristotle refers to as that which is part of the concupiscible (from the Latin, concupiscere, “desire” in English) powers[iii]. In analyzing romance (at least in this essay), we should look at it in the lens of love in the third sense of the term.
          We cannot speak of it in the first sense, since it is improper to speak of God’s love as romantic, for romantic love wills, or desires a good, other than oneself for one’s perfection, but God doesn’t will anything other than Himself for His perfection, for His Nature fits Him for Himself, and so His Will gravitates to Himself alone. He, therefore, is involved in eternal, self-sufficient, self-loving, which is not what romantic love is[iv].
          We may speak of romantic love in light of the supernatural virtue of charity, or in light of the second sense. For, being an effect of grace under justification, together with faith and hope[v], it elevates and heals human nature in all its aspects, including man’s ability to be attracted romantically. But this would entail that we will no longer speak of it as it is considered by itself. Also, this is unnecessary, for even the man who lacks the said virtue is still able to fall in love. So, for the purposes of this essay, we will set aside Charity and just focus on discussing romantic love in light of the third, or last, sense: love as a passion.
          But first: what is a passion[vi]? A passion is, let’s just say for simplicity’s sake, an emotive power of the soul. It’s what we call a “feeling” or “emotion”. When you feel sad when watching a movie involving heavy drama, that’s a passion. When you feel happy because your favorite team won the championship, that’s a passion.
          Let’s expand our thoughts a little more. According to Aristotle, Aquinas, and Catholic teaching, humans have souls. And our souls have certain abilities that we either (1) share with all living things, (2) with other animals, or (3) is unique to us as rational animals. An example of (1) is the power of nutrition, or the preservation of bodily existence, a power we exercise when we eat or get nutrients. An example of (2) is locomotion, or movement, or our ability to move from one place to another. An example of (3) is our intellect, or the seat of intellectual cognition, which enables us to do things like solve mathematical problems.
          The passions are part of what we share with other animals, but it is important also to emphasize the fact that the passions don’t exist in us in the same way it exists in animals like, say, a dog. The lower powers of the soul that we share with other living things are elevated in a higher state due to the fact that we have an existentially higher form of soul, called the rational soul. Our rational powers perfect our lower appetites and integrate them into our higher human life. An example of this is how our power of nutrition is elevated given our rationality: we have attached a cultural significance to eating in a way that mere animal eating doesn’t have, like in birthday parties, or receptions, to give concrete examples. It’s important to remember this as we progress in the topic of this essay.
          The passions, which are individual parts of our appetite, are our response to sense cognition, or our interaction to the external world through sensation. We have 5 external senses (and we all know these): sight, smell, taste, touch, and hearing. We also have 4 internal senses, according to Aquinas: common sense, or that which coordinates sense knowledge; imagination, or that which furnishes sense images; estimative power, or “animal reason”; and sense memory, or that which stores sense impressions[vii]. When these powers are used, we either desire what we sensed because it is good, or we evade it because it is bad. This power to pursue the lovable and to flee what is hateful is what appetite is in general. It is the passions when we specify.
          To understand this better, consider this statement: “That barbeque sure smells delicious! Reminds me of the barbeque from my favorite restaurant. I can’t wait to eat it.” What we have here is a statement based on sense cognition that lead to a response from the appetite: the one who spoke the statement first smelled the barbeque (exercise of the external power of smell) which reminded him of the barbeque from his favorite restaurant (exercise of the internal power of sense memory) that lead him to crave it or to want to eat it (exercise of the passion of desire).
          Once again, our appetitive powers are elevated due to our rationality. Animals only have mere sense appetite, since they have no power to think of or love the good or hate the bad the way we do. Our appetite is different from them. We call it the will. It inclines us to what we, not only sense, but apprehend as good or fitting. It’s object it the known good (since we cannot love, or hate, what we do not know). The will is also the seat of our freedom, which allows us to choose the multiple means by which we can go to our ends that we know is good for us.
          There’s still a lot going on here other than what I have just expounded on. What is important is for us to grasp the basics I have just given. Now, let us focus on the passion of love and what it entails with regards to romance.
The Passion of Love
          Love is the root of the passions[viii]. We are only inclined to move towards that which we know is lovable, or good (remember, once again, the quote from St. Augustine above). This gives us a definition of loving: it is the recognition that something else is fitting for me, that something is good for me. And in encountering these goods infused in our nature (a good meal for lunch, a friend, a new knowledge about the truth) causes in us a sense of longing, that feeling of “that should be for me, that should be me mine, it is for me”.
          Aquinas cites Pseudo-Dionysius in saying that love is a “vis unitiva” or a unitive power[ix]. It unites us to our beloved in two ways: it unites us to the goods that build us up, as we are united with food as a digestive or nutritive good; and drives us to achieve real union by moving us to “grab” the good, as we are driven to cook in order to be able to achieve the good of eating.
          It is also important to point out that love is divided in two: “towards the good which a man wishes to someone (to himself or to another) and towards that to which he wishes some good[x]. In other words, it is divided into love of concupiscence (“towards the good”), and love of friendship (“towards that to which he wishes some good”). To set up the main course of this essay, let’s use this example: A man is drawn towards courting (love of concupiscence, to the good), but he is drawn to it not just for the sake of courtship, he is drawn to it to win the heart of the woman he loves (love of friendship, to the person).
          Love is a concupiscible passion. The concupiscible appetite is that which responds to a “sensible good or evil, simply apprehended as such, which causes pleasure or pain.”[xi] The concupiscible passions are those passions that respond to simple goods or evils, in contrast to the irascible passions, which concerns goods/evils that are difficult to achieve/avoid. Now, do I think romantic love just belongs to the concupiscible passions per se? No, and I don’t think Aquinas, in his genius, will say otherwise. Initially, I would say that romance is indeed a concupiscible passion, but it may turn into something irascible depending on the circumstances, just like other goods. More on this later.

Application of Thomistic principles to Romantic Love

CAUSES AND EFFECTS OF LOVE
          Having all the background ideas in place, let’s look at the passion of love in greater detail but now focusing on romance.
          What causes romantic attraction? Let’s answer this by asking what causes love in general.
          Aquinas lists three causes of love[xii]. First, goodness: the object must first present itself as a perfection, a good, something that is desirable. This may be something superficial at first - the beloved’s beautiful eyes, or the beloved’s good singing voice, probably even the beloved’s dorky personality – but it is a good nonetheless.
          Second, knowledge: you cannot love what you don’t know. What is good in the beloved is apprehended by the lover: “she really has beautiful eyes…I like the way he sings”. The lover knows that a good is possessed by the beloved, and he aims to get hold of it.
          Third, likeness: the beloved should be, in some way or another, akin, or similar, to the lover. The man who courts a woman or who wants to grab a woman’s attention may appeal to their similarities to enkindle interest to the woman: “What’s your favorite food? Really? That’s crazy because that’s my favorite too!” In order to develop love, there has to be a “same-ness” to begin with.
          So, these are the causes of romantic love. We are all able to relate, aren’t we?
          What about the effects of love? Aquinas lists four[xiii].
          First, union: love seeks the presence of the beloved. We miss our loves if they aren’t present.  Second, mutual indwelling: the lover finds, or searches for, the beloved, while the beloved dwells in the lover’s mind. This is what makes the lover say “you’re always on my mind”.
          Third, ecstasy: the lover “stands outside of himself” in pursuit of the beloved. And fourth, zeal: every obstacle or impediment is opposed by the lover so that he may be able to enjoy the presence of his love. Calum Scott probably said it best in his song, You are the Reason: “I’d climb every mountain, and swim every ocean just to be with you…”

PASSIONS THAT FOLLOW FROM LOVE    

          In the Summa Theologiae, Prima Secundae, Questions 30 and 31, Aquinas discusses the two passions that follow from love.
          If the beloved is absent, love gives rise to desire or concupiscence[xiv]: this is defined as “love in motion”. Since the beloved is not with the lover, the love that proceeds from the lover is a love that seeks, a love that is restless, that finds. I guess you can call this the philosophy behind missing someone. Desire is what makes someone say “I’m officially missing you”.
          If, on the other hand, the beloved is present, love gives rise to pleasure. If desire is love in motion, then pleasure is just “love at rest”. The lover’s love is a contented love, simply enjoying the fact that the one loved is right there with him. Pleasure is when you are able to put your head on his shoulder, or rest on his chest to feel his heartbeat, or embrace him with all your arms wide open. “I’d rather have bad times with you, than good times with someone else,” says Luther Vandross, “I’d rather have the one who holds my heart”. Vandross’ lyrics aim for pleasure. This is the type of love we all long for, not just with regards to romance, but with all the goods we long for.
Romance as an Irascible Passion
          Si crush, parang exam: pag hindi mo makuha, tititigan mo na lang.
Attraction is an easy thing, but the challenge is getting what attracts you. Commonly, this involves a lot of obstacles: knowing her favorite food or color, winning her friends’ approval, making sure you ask her “have you eaten already?” every meal time. Expressing love involves many duties. The question is: can the lover do it all?
          This is where, I think, romantic love is, at certain circumstances, turned into an irascible passion. Once again, irascible passions are those passions that recognizes a difficulty in achieving the good (or avoid the bad). So, when it comes to, specifically, courtship or pleasing one’s beloved, we need not only to ask the question of “Is this a good thing?”. We should also consider “Should I approach this? How do I approach this? This seems challenging.”
          Since the good is seen as difficult to achieve (or the bad as difficult to shun), the person should now inquire whether he attacks or proceeds, or flee, before the difficult good or evil. Torpe ka ba o hindi? That’s the question.
          Now, Aquinas lists five irascible powers, but for the sake of this essay, all we have to focus on is the first two powers he discusses in the Summa: hope and despair[xv].
          Hope is the response if the “difficult thing is (still) something possible to obtain[xvi]. It is that which moves us to achieve a good, even if it is difficult. Despite the obstacles, the lover still aims to grasp the beloved because he still can. Even if the lover might need to go through a lot of challenges, he senses that the good is still able to be achieved, and so he proceeds, even if it means catching a grenade or jumping in front of the train for the beloved, as Bruno Mars once said in his song, grenade. Bruno may be exaggerating, but you get the point. Those who pursue the beloved confidently even if it is hard to do so are filled with the passion of hope.
          Despair is the passion that is felt for the good “in so far as it is considered as unobtainable[xvii]. So, if hope is the response to an achievable good despite the difficulty, despair is the response to an unachievable good. What this causes to the lover is to draw back, to give up, you might say, in pursuing the beloved, since the beloved is just beyond himself. “Naliligaw at malayo ang tanaw. Pinipigilan na ang pusong pinipilit ay ikaw.” This is the response of either the unconfident lover (torpe), or the lover who thinks his beloved is just far beyond himself (“she’s so beautiful; look at me, an ugly dude”). The hopeless romantic is filled with despair.
          That is the outline of the Thomistic philosophical analysis on what happens with romance as related to the passions. But remember what we’ve said awhile ago: our abilities are elevated due to our rational soul. So, how exactly are romantic feelings elevated by our ability to think and love and choose?

Romance and Rationality

          It is important to note, first and foremost, that the fact that we are able to be romantically attracted to someone is already a product of rationality. Remember that we have different appetites compared to mere animals, who have no rationality in them at all. Scooby-doo, for instance, since he is just a dog, can only be moved by the sense appetite, by instinct, you might say. He may be moved by the smell of meat, but he cannot apprehend, judge, or reason[xviii] about the meat (despite the things the Scooby-doo cartoon shows, such as Scooby-doo being able to talk, for the capacity for language flows from rationality only). He cannot say or think, “Oh, this meat is chicken meat. Chicken meat can be fried or not… it can be used in different recipes”. A man like Shaggy, though, can do those things, and he can be moved towards the goods he is inclined to by the will, not just his instincts.
          Apply these things to the inclination of animated things to the good of reproduction[xix] (to preserve the fullness of being to the next generation of being) and what you get is precisely the essence of romantic attraction. Reproduction is a power we share with all the living things, not just animals, for even plants reproduce. Here’s the thing, though: we’re not just animals or plants, and so our capability for reproduction is integrated in our higher, rational, human life. Remember the example we used awhile ago: our ability to absorb nutrition through eating is integrated into our rationality, and so we have attached a social and cultural significance to eating, as evident in parties.
          The same thing’s true for our capacity to reproduce. Our reproductive powers are elevated due to our humanity. Where does this lead to? This leads to the concept of romance, in which the concepts of marriage and the human family are integral parts. This is interesting since this means that in Aquinas’ philosophy (and in Catholicism in general), marriage is a natural institution that flows exactly from human nature. It’s not just something man made up for himself. This means that marriage cannot just be altered by human law. Of course, the ethics surrounding marriage and the issues attached to it (as to whether same-sex marriage should be legalized, for instance) is beyond the scope of this essay. The point is that romance, which is uniquely a human ability, doesn’t stop in itself. It points to even more complex, more beautiful things in which we as humans are tied to, all because we are human.

Conclusion

          There’s a lot to talk about with regards romance, of course, and not all of them can be analyzed and exposed in here. Topics like the role of the passions in human flourishing in general, for instance, can be a great topic to discuss. But I think I have done my job properly: to look at romantic feelings in the lens of the Angelic Doctor through his philosophy on the passions. Now it is clear to us as to what is the philosophy behind falling in love, missing someone, and desiring to marry and raise a family with our beloved. Now it is evident to us what lies behind our being crazy over someone.
          Romance is indeed a very complex thing, but we now, at least, know where it comes from and how it works in us humans.
          It is my hope that this essay gives clarity to romance using Aquinas’ philosophy as basis. I also hope that this arouses a desire to the intellect of the reader to pursue a search for Thomistic philosophy, to love reality as Aquinas saw it.
         
         



[i] St. Augustine’s Confessions, 13, 9, 10
[ii] Peter Kreeft, Practical Theology, p. 91
[iii] Aristotle, Topics ii, 7
[iv] To see more about Aquinas’ exposition on the Will of God, See Summa Theologiae, Prima Pars, QQ. 19-21
[v] 1 Corinthians 13:13, also Summa Theologiae, Prima Secundae, Q. 113
[vi] Summa Theologiae, Prima Secundae, QQ. 22-48
[vii] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 78, aa. 3-4
[viii] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 26, a. 2, reply to Objection 1
[ix] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 26, a. 2, reply to Objection 2
[x] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 26, a. 4, “I answer that…”
[xi] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 23, a. 1, “I answer that…”
[xii] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 27, aa. 1-3
[xiii] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 28, aa. 1-4
[xiv] It is once again important to remember that we are just using the term “concupiscence” as a synonym for desire. There is nothing in the term as currently used as connected to the effects of original sin or even with regards to mere sexual desire or lust as it is commonly used today.
[xv] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 40
[xvi] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 40, a. 1 “I answer that…”, emphasis added
[xvii] Ibid., Prima Secundae, Q. 40, a. 4 “I answer that…”, emphasis added
[xviii]  Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s The Posterior Analytics
[xix] To see more on Aquinas’ treatment on the powers of the soul, see Summa Theologiae, Prima Secundae, QQ. 77-83

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Wanna Make Things Right? Stop Prioritizing Justice

  Image by  Jill Wellington  from  Pixabay It seems to me that there is an intuitive sense within us fallen human beings to prioritize justice in a cold, blind sense before everything else. Yes, even before love or friendship, we aim to make sure that we are given our due and that people who have hurt us should be hurt as well, so that he or she can feel what we also felt. For instance, if we learn that a person we consider a friend is actually stabbing us in the back, the reasonable response seems to be to break the friendship apart and complain about this same friend to other people. This seems what is just in our eyes. And for us, as long as our sense of blind justice is preserved, all will be well. But for Christ, making things right does not mean prioritizing justice in the retributive sense of the word. Rather, for Him, justice is merely secondary to gratuitous, no-holds-barred Divine Mercy. Mercy always and everywhere is primary. Only when Mercy precedes justice can things be ma

A Man Motivated By Love

Image by  Francesco Nigro  from  Pixabay First, a word about the 1988 movie The Truman Show starring Jim Carrey.  In the said movie, the main character, Truman Burbank (played by Carrey) lived in the biggest studio ever, which he thought was the real world, since he was the baby. Basically, everything around him is fake. He would interact with other people in his "island" not knowing they were simply paid actors. In short, he is living a life ruled by deception.  But there was a moment in his life where he met a woman named "Lauren" (whose real name is Sylvia), and fell in love with her. Lauren was also the first person in the whole show to tell Truman that he was living a lie, because in reality, she is a member of the "Free Truman" movement. Unfortunately, so that Truman would not know the truth, "Lauren" was taken off the show. To make the long story short, she became the motivating factor for Truman to leave his Island, a voyage which would u

Saint Thomas Aquinas, My Beloved Professor in Heaven: The four most important lessons I learned from the Angelic Doctor

                 It’s been three years since I first discovered and seriously personally studied the works of Saint Thomas Aquinas, and I can happily say that I am far from really scratching the surface. The Angelic Doctor has this awe-inspiring gift of deep insight when it comes to philosophical and theological truths; this great awareness of both the metaphysics of the cosmos and the infinite divine power and love that moves the planets, of both what things are in themselves and He Who Is, of the words that come from the wisdom of antiquity and the Word that breathes forth Love, Who is the Logos of God through Which the Father expresses His design in creation and through Which the Father recreates us in redemption. In short, Aquinas’s thought is this one, big, wholesome vision of God, our First Cause and Last End, and His mysterious and astonishing relationship with the universe that one cannot really claim to be an “expert” when it comes to his teachings (one can have a specialty in