Socialism: A Leonine Critique

           


Thought experiment: Imagine you’re in middle-to-late 19th-century England. New opportunities arise for you, as an able-bodied adult, when it comes to making money. Instead of remaining in your rural village to farm, you decided to give the factory a shot. But once you step into the city, problems with this new industrial system immediately make themselves evident: harsh working conditions, inhumane treatment of workers, unreasonably low wages, and even child labor. You know you want such a system to change. Deep inside, it is obvious that there are blatant violations of man’s rights in such circumstances. The question is: What is the right solution?

 

          This is the historical situation that moved Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels to publish in 1848 The Communist Manifesto. With Marx’s hegelian-inspired, materialistic view of history as one big class struggle between the ruling class/bourgeoisie and the working class/proletariat as theoretical backdrop,[1] the two saw that the best means toward renewing society’s mistreatment of workers is nothing less than a revolution: “Let the ruling classes tremble at a Communistic revolution. The proletarians (poor workers) have nothing to lose but their chains. They have a world to win.”[2]

 

What is Socialism?

 

But if revolution is the means, what is communism’s end? Marx couldn’t be more clear: “the theory of the Communists may be summed up in the single sentence: abolition of private property.”[3] In other words, for communism, the solution to the so-called tyrannical control of industry by the ruling class is to strip them of the private ownership of the means of production of goods and services so that they’d be communally owned.[4] The Communist Party of the Philippines, in their official constitution and program, is also very explicit about this goal: “The private ownership of the means of production and distribution by the big bourgeoisie and landlord class must be abolished.”[5] This is so that there’d be no hierarchy of social classes, but only a classless society, a society which, in the mind of the communists, would be promoting equality and fairness to its citizens.

 

This politico-economic theory, which advocates for “taking away the source of capitalists’ power (which is) the private ownership of property,”[6] is otherwise known as socialism. To once again quote the Communist Party of the Philippines, this is a socio-political vision in which “(p)ublic ownership of the means of production shall become dominant and state economic planning will direct the development of a well-balanced socialist economy… After the socialist transformation of industry and the entire economy, the Party shall ensure that there is no retrogression into private ownership of the means of production.[7] More precisely defined, socialism “concerns government ownership and control over basic[8] means for the production and distribution of goods.”[9]

 

“Hold on a minute,” you might ask, “I thought socialism advocates for the social/communal ownership of the sources of goods and services; why is it now defined as government/state ownership of the same?” It’s simple, really: If, for instance, the agricultural industry is to be owned by all (as was the aspirations of socialist rulers like Stalin and Mao)[10] so that all can be provided for, someone has to be in charge to regulate it and see its proper distribution, which is none other than the state. So, at the end of the day, communal ownership isn’t really communal in the strict sense when it comes to socialism. It’s more of a state control of a nation's economic sector; we can thus call a socialist economy a command/planned economy.[11]

 

Now that we have properly defined what socialism is, we now have to ask: Is this the right solution to the socio-economic ills not only during Marx’s time, but ours as well?

 

Here Comes the Lion

 

            The social conditions in which Marx formulated his communist-socialist vision are also the same contexts that Pope Leo XIII (d. 1903) wished to address in what is now considered the “first social encyclical,”[12] Rerum Novarum[13] (English translation: “new things”), published on May 15, 1891. Just like Marx, Pope Leo saw many problems in the “new things” of the industrial revolution, particularly regarding the circumstances in which workers find themselves. Among other things, he saw “the utter poverty of the masses,” “moral degeneracy,” “rapacious usury,” and the “misery and wretchedness pressing so unjustly on the majority of the working class.”[14]

 

But the similarities between the two end there. Marx and Leo may have diagnosed the same disease, but they have provided cures that can’t be more different. As a matter of fact, the latter even went so far as to say that the socialist solution to the industrial problem, which is “to do away with property,”[15] is a cure worse than the disease: “their (i.e. the socialists) contentions are so clearly powerless to end the controversy that were they carried into effect the working man himself would be among the first to suffer. They are, moreover, emphatically unjust, for they would rob the lawful possessor, distort the functions of the State, and create utter confusion in the community.”[16]

 

So, Pope Leo XIII is explicit: socialism is a terrible solution to the problem. Why did he think so? His position can be summed up into three reasons: Socialism is wrong because (1) it goes against the natural right to private property, (2) it violates the principle of subsidiarity and the rights of the family, and (3) it restricts personal freedom of initiative to take on diverse interests and jobs, which will generate diverse and unequal outcomes and wages.

 

Let’s take a look at these two reasons and why, in my estimation, these reasons make a good case against socialism.

 

Socialism vs Private Property

 

We’ve already seen that socialism is against the private ownership of property. For the sake of precision, however, it would be helpful if we can define exactly what it means to own something. The philosopher Edward Feser provides a helpful definition of ownership:

 

(T)o own something is essentially to possess a bundle of rights over the thing.  For example, suppose I own a certain pencil.What that involves is my having the right to use the pencil whenever I want to, the right to lend it to others if I so desire, the right not to lend it to them if that’s what I prefer, the right to chew on it if I feel anxious, the right to break it in half if I want to shorten it or simply as a way to take out frustration, and so forth.To own the pencil is to have a bundle of such rights, and to have such a bundle of rights over the pencil is to own it.[17]

 

          So, to own something is to have a right to be able to dispose of it in an autonomous fashion. Of course, you have the obvious moral and legal limits to such an autonomous use/disuse, but overall, this sounds like a very intuitive definition that all of us can agree upon. If I own something, I can do with it whatever I like (within moral and legal limits, of course).

 

          Common sense also tells us that the right to own private property is a natural right, or a right that springs forth from us simply by being human, not by some deliberate contractual obligation or state imposition. Leo XIII says that, when it comes to said right:

 

There is no need to bring in the State. Man precedes the State, and possesses, prior to the formation of any State, the right of providing for the substance of his body.[18]

 

          I have the natural right to own food/ingredients that can help me cook food, because I have the right to feed myself for the sake of self-preservation. And this right was not arbitrarily given to me. It’s simply a consequence of my being human. Take note, I have a natural right to own, not just access, goods that I will need to preserve myself. Access to goods is all an animal needs to have. If an elephant is thirsty, all he needs to do is drink from a lake. But unlike animals, humans have intellects, which not only tells us what we need at the present but allows us to discern and prepare for the future. The conclusion is obvious: We must therefore not just have goods for today or at this moment; we must also keep and safeguard things (and the source for such things) for future use, which is just another way to say we have the right to own private property.

 

It is the mind, or reason, which is the predominant element in us who are human creatures; it is this which renders a human being human, and distinguishes him essentially from the brute. And on this very account - that man alone among the animal creation is endowed with reason - it must be within his right to possess things not merely for temporary and momentary use, as other living things do, but to have and to hold them in stable and permanent possession; he must have not only things that perish in the use, but those also which, though they have been reduced into use, continue for further use in after time…

 

For man, fathoming by his faculty of reason matters without number, linking the future with the present, and being master of his own acts, guides his ways under the eternal law and the power of God, whose providence governs all things. Wherefore, it is in his power to exercise his choice not only as to matters that regard his present welfare, but also about those which he deems may be for his advantage in time yet to come. Hence, man not only should possess the fruits of the earth, but also the very soil, inasmuch as from the produce of the earth he has to lay by provision for the future.[19]

 

          The consequence of such reasoning is also obvious: If ownership of private property is a natural right, then the socialist aspiration to abolish it is a violation of a natural right, and hence must be condemned.

 

          What would happen if we abolished private property and opted instead for a system where property of goods and services are socially/communally owned and excessively regulated by the state? Simply put: the consequences would be disastrous.

 

          First, such a system will succumb to what economist Friedrich Hayek called the “synoptic delusion” or “the knowledge problem.” Fr. Robert Sirico describes it this way:

 

The synoptic (one-eyed) delusion is the notion that a single analyst – not necessarily a single individual, but a single entity or agency – can accurately comprehend and assess the entire range of information necessary to predictably manipulate a complex social organism such as a modern culture or economy.[20]

 

In other words, a single person/body of persons cannot know the exact ways to navigate economic matters, like pricing, for knowledge in such matters are dispersed through every single individual, since they are the ones who know their wants and needs, and not a single individual or group. But this is exactly the problem of socialism: Socialists want economic knowledge to be centralized/isolated in a single system, which is impossible. For example, how will we know if there’s a shortage in the production of bread given, say, a lack of resources to make it? In a free market system, such knowledge could be communicated to all by the setting of prices: those who produce flour and eggs that can make bread will increase the prices for said produces in order to properly manage the scarce resources by regulating customer consumption and so that the producers can have more funds/incentives to produce more of it. On the other hand, if there’s an abundance of said ingredients, then these same producers will lower the prices to incentivize consumers to buy more of it and to discourage producers from making too much of something that is not too profitable.[21]

 

And herein lies the socialist problem: Without multiple producers and consumers who represent the wants, needs, and resources of the collective through privately owned businesses and enterprises, only the state can arbitrarily set prices and/or produce (or not produce) goods, which will inevitably fail to reflect the law of supply and demand among the people, which would then lead to the overproduction of supplies that have little to no demand and underproduction of supplies that have so much demand. This is because such a society will have statesmen relying on guess work in terms of production instead of the more reliable price system that free societies have and which we have explained above.

 

This is exactly what happened in the USSR. As Trent Horn and Dr. Catherine Pakaluk noted: “(U)nlike capitalist economies that allow prices (and production) to adjust according to consumer choice, the Soviet system set rigid production targets, and consumers just had to ‘choose’ whatever was offered to them.”[22] In other words, because the Soviet Union relied on production quotas instead of prices, the people had no choice but to take what was produced, instead of what they really wanted or needed. The negative effects of this were felt during the reign of Joseph Stalin who, because he wanted to prioritize national defense, “focused on heavy industry at the expense of things like food production.”[23] Because he arbitrarily chose to produce more with regards steel and the like instead of food (not to mention his forced confiscation of Ukrainian farms for the sake of his “project”), this led to people (who’d naturally prefer food over steel) starving to death. This famine, which lasted from 1932-1933, killed 5 million.[24] This is the effect of not letting the people themselves decide what they need to own and buy to preserve themselves and presuming that only one person or party can determine that for everyone. A lot of evil things can indeed happen if you violate a natural right.

 

But besides the knowledge problem, socialism’s desire of centralizing instead of freeing the economy at the hands of the people also creates what can be called “the incentive problem” or what I prefer to call “the public bathroom problem.” To explain what this is, it would be helpful to cite an example from history.

 

In the year 1620, the so-called Plymouth Colony, one of the first few English colonies in America, decided to grow their food communally and distributed it equally to all who belong to their colony, including those who didn’t work for the growth of the foods. For someone sympathetic to socialist principles, this sounds like paradise. But nothing could be further from the truth: “The result was economic chaos, disease, starvation, death, and the near extinction of the first New England settlers.”[25] How did this happen?

 

Think about it: If I, who works hard in the communal farm, will get the same amount of food as the one who works less than me or is too lazy to work for the community, then why would I bother working hard, not to mention working at all? Also, the complaint of the young men in the colony was: Why would I work for the sustenance of someone else’s wife and children if those aren’t my family? Why can’t the husband and father of that same family work for themselves?[26]

 

The result was that the workers lost the incentive to work because the lazy man got the same ration of food as the hardworking man anyway. But if no one’s working or at least starts working less than before, then this will lead to decreased production, which will lead to inevitable death by starvation the less incentives there are to work and the less productions of food occur.

 

How did the colony solve this problem? It’s simple: the people were allowed to own portions of the land and let them work for their own sustenance. “The result was the first plentiful harvest and the first bountiful thanksgiving.”[27]

 

This is, once again, common sense. People work to get paid for the sake of self-preservation. And this is not selfishness, this is natural self-interest, which everyone has: You eat and drink for yourself; it follows that you will also work for food and drink for yourself. If we can get these goods for free every time, no one will work. Getting paid fairly and being able to procure goods through the wage is a natural incentive for working. As Pope Leo XIII said:

 

It is surely undeniable that, when a man engages in remunerative labor, the impelling reason and motive of his work is to obtain property, and thereafter to hold it as his very own. If one man hires out to another his strength or skill, he does so for the purpose of receiving in return what is necessary for the satisfaction of his needs; he therefore expressly intends to acquire a right full and real, not only to the remuneration, but also to the disposal of such remuneration, just as he pleases… Socialists, therefore, by endeavoring to transfer the possessions of individuals to the community at large, strike at the interests of every wage-earner, since they would deprive him of the liberty of disposing of his wages, and thereby of all hope and possibility of increasing his resources and of bettering his condition in life.[28]

 

No one would bother working if, in the name of “equality” and “community,” I can get the same amount of goods as the one who doesn’t work by a deliberate choice. And because no one would find it reasonable to work, the result will be production decrease, as noted above, and the ruin of society will be inevitable, as in what happened in the Plymouth Colony.

 

This is why I also call this “the public bathroom problem.” There’s a reason why public bathrooms are generally dirtier and nastier than our bathrooms at home: There’s not much incentive to clean the former, because someone else can clean it for me (i.e. janitors and other good-willed people), with the result being that most of the time it isn’t even cleaned well or not cleaned at all. On the other hand, we prefer to clean the latter because it belongs to us. Same thing with property ownership and access to goods: If I can work to own it for the sake of my own survival, then great. But if it can be guaranteed that I can have access to these goods without even working (because someone else will work on my behalf), then I’d rather not work, with the inevitable result being that no one will (want to) work, unless, of course, the state forces us to work, which leads to the problem of tyranny, the major issue of all socialist states throughout history – from Russia to North Korea.

 

Socialism vs The Family (and Subsidiarity)

 

            As noted above, man “precedes the state” and thus has natural rights, like the right to private property, “prior to the formation of any State.”          But these natural rights flow from man’s natural dispositions. Look again at the right to private property. Man has a right to private property because, by nature, he is disposed to plan his life ahead of time and thus has to have ownership of goods in accordance with this plan. But besides our rational disposition or ability to plan our lives, we also have the disposition not just to preserve ourselves but our species, which can be done through the raising of a family, enabled through the procreation between persons who differ in sex: Man and woman. Humans, who have a disposition to procreate and preserve the human species, thus have a natural right to marry and have children, a right that is also independent of the state:

 

The rights here spoken of, belonging to each individual man, are seen in much stronger light when considered in relation to man's social and domestic obligations. In choosing a state of life, it is indisputable that all are at full liberty to follow the counsel of Jesus Christ as to observing virginity, or to bind themselves by the marriage tie. No human law can abolish the natural and original right of marriage, nor in any way limit the chief and principal purpose of marriage ordained by God's authority from the beginning: "Increase and multiply."(3) Hence we have the family, the "society" of a man's house - a society very small, one must admit, but none the less [sic] a true society, and one older than any State. Consequently, it has rights and duties peculiar to itself which are quite independent of the State.[29]

 

          The consequence of this natural right, Pope Leo XIII said, also affects the right to private property. Here’s a helpful way of thinking about it: If X has a right toward Y, then Y has a duty toward X. An analogy might be helpful: just as a statesman has a duty toward the nation, like safeguarding the public peace, this means that it goes hand in hand with the nation’s right to have its peace maintained. If a student has a right to be educated, then a teacher has a duty to educate. I hope it’s clear: My duty to do something to others implies the rights of the others to be served by me. Rights and duties, in other words, are relational realities. It makes sense through a reference to another person.

 

          Now, when it comes to the family, the person (Pope Leo specifies the father)[30] who freely enters married/family life obviously has the duty to provide for his family. But remember: duties are accompanied by rights. So if the father has the duty to provide for his family, then he has the right to be able to keep for himself the goods (or the sources of such goods) that will allow him to fulfill this duty – like a house or food supply accessed and bought through just wages. We can see here that the right to private property is “extended,” so to speak, to one’s familial duties so that one not only has the right to own for oneself, but also for those he’s responsible towards.

 

That right to property, therefore, which has been proved to belong naturally to individual persons, must in like wise [sic] belong to a man in his capacity of head of a family; nay, that right is all the stronger in proportion as the human person receives a wider extension in the family group. It is a most sacred law of nature that a father should provide food and all necessaries for those whom he has begotten; and, similarly, it is natural that he should wish that his children, who carry on, so to speak, and continue his personality, should be by him provided with all that is needful to enable them to keep themselves decently from want and misery amid the uncertainties of this mortal life. Now, in no other way can a father effect this except by the ownership of productive property, which he can transmit to his children by inheritance. A family, no less than a State, is, as We have said, a true society, governed by an authority peculiar to itself, that is to say, by the authority of the father. Provided, therefore, the limits which are prescribed by the very purposes for which it exists be not transgressed, the family has at least equal rights with the State in the choice and pursuit of the things needful to its preservation and its just liberty. We say, "at least equal rights"; for, inasmuch as the domestic household is antecedent, as well in idea as in fact, to the gathering of men into a community, the family must necessarily have rights and duties which are prior to those of the community, and founded more immediately in nature. If the citizens, if the families on entering into association and fellowship, were to experience hindrance in a commonwealth instead of help, and were to find their rights attacked instead of being upheld, society would rightly be an object of detestation rather than of desire.[31]

 

          Just as taking away the ownership of an individual in the name of collectivism is a violation of a natural right as we saw above, then it is also a violation of a natural right for other groups/societies “above” the family to take away this parental responsibility and make it their own. Leo XIII formulates this obvious conclusion:

 

The contention, then, that the civil government should at its option intrude into and exercise intimate control over the family and the household is a great and pernicious error. True, if a family finds itself in exceeding distress, utterly deprived of the counsel of friends, and without any prospect of extricating itself, it is right that extreme necessity be met by public aid, since each family is a part of the commonwealth. In like manner, if within the precincts of the household there occur grave disturbance of mutual rights, public authority should intervene to force each party to yield to the other its proper due; for this is not to deprive citizens of their rights, but justly and properly to safeguard and strengthen them. But the rulers of the commonwealth must go no further; here, nature bids them stop. Paternal authority can be neither abolished nor absorbed by the State; for it has the same source as human life itself. "The child belongs to the father," and is, as it were, the continuation of the father's personality; and speaking strictly, the child takes its place in civil society, not of its own right, but in its quality as member of the family in which it is born. And for the very reason that "the child belongs to the father" it is, as St. Thomas Aquinas says, "before it attains the use of free will, under the power and the charge of its parents." The socialists, therefore, in setting aside the parent and setting up a State supervision, act against natural justice, and destroy the structure of the home.[32]

 

If it isn’t obvious yet why this is such a big deal, allow me to explain further. Fr. Sirico argues that private property is such an important right that, when we take it away, we take away other rights that depend on it. He puts it this way:

 

If you are to have a right to free speech, but are not permitted to publish a book at a private publisher, or to own a newspaper or TV or radio station, or (increasingly) even to post an opinion online because the government has begun to treat the internet as if it owns it, then in what practical sense can you be said to have the right to free speech?

 

The same is true of religion. If the state strips away our economic freedom to decide how and where we use our private means to compensate doctors, nurses, and physical therapists in exchange for medical care, if the government comes to control all of this as if these medical skills and private exchanges were somehow the government’s property, then it suddenly becomes easier for the government to infringe upon one’s right to religious freedom in certain important ways… (like) the Obama Administration’s Department of Health and Human Services in early 2012, requiring religious institutions to provide abortifacient drugs, sterilization, and contraception coverage as part of their health insurance programs even if those religious groups are morally opposed to doing so.[33]

 

            In other words, if you take away private property, you take away man’s initiative in making his quality of life better in a way that would correspond to other natural rights, like free speech and religious liberty. The right to ownership is so fundamental that, if you abolish it, you abolish many other rights together with it, uprooting a tree so that it bears fruit no more.

 

          Let me give another example. If the state takes away a husband and father’s right to dispose of his wages in the best way possible – like the right to use it for his children’s tuition or to buy books or school materials – then the state not only took away his right to private property, it also took away his right to educate his children or choose the best possible education system his children needs. This is the “great and pernicious error” that Leo XIII condemns.

 

          This would also give rise to the problems mentioned in the previous section, like the knowledge problem. As I would like to say: The man from Malacañang does not lose sleep regarding whether or not I’ve already eaten dinner. That concern is for the parents and closest relatives/friends only. Also, what if my problem is not lack of food, but lack of self control in consuming food? The people from the highest of offices won’t know that. If they take the role of parents instead of my actual parents, then if they misjudge that the people in my home need more food supply, that will be to my health’s detriment. My family would’ve known that what I needed was to spend money on diet products and gym membership.

 

          This is why Marx and Engels saw the family as a threat to their collectivist mentality. Just like their disdain for private property, they were very clear that abolishing the family is part and parcel with their desire for a communal ownership of goods: “Abolition of the family! Even the most radical flare up at this infamous proposal of the Communists.”[34] The connection is clear: Any good parent will want to shield his family from outside forces that (at least in his judgment) can corrupt his children’s moral formation and is more inclined to help his family before the larger community (this is also common sense: we know there’s a huge difference, morally speaking, between a man who fails to feed his next-door neighbor and a man who fails to feed his own children; the latter is more morally depraved). But at the heart of the communist-socialist ideal is that these so-called “outside forces” and “larger community” are the priority over any smaller group such as the family (see the definition of “socialism” above), because “(c)entral to the meaning of socialism is common ownership. This means the resources of the world being owned in common by the entire global population.”[35] Therefore, if the family hinders the progress of the collective, we have to sacrifice and abolish it.

 

          This is why the push for a stronger and more centralized government will inevitably weaken the family unit, while a stronger family unit is a form of resistance to such efforts. You can only fight for one or the other. You cannot have both. Feser states:

 

(T)he more the traditional family structure breaks down, the more individuals there are – especially single mothers and children – who find themselves without sufficient private means of support, and thus require greater governmental assistance.  This plausibly accounts for what social scientists have called the “marriage gap” in U.S. voting patterns. Both married men and married women are likelier [sic] to vote for conservative candidates.  By contrast, unmarried men are significantly more likely to vote for liberal candidates, and unmarried women are massively more likely to vote for liberal candidates.  If you are a breadwinner capable of supporting a family or the spouse of such a breadwinner, you are less likely to need state assistance and are bound to resent the government taxing away income that could be used for the benefit of your family.  By contrast, if you do not have a family to support you will be less resentful of taxation, and you are single mother with children or a woman unable to find a husband you are bound to regard government as a kind of surrogate provider.[36]

 

          Remember that many other rights (like the right to educate one’s children) presuppose private property such that if you take away the former, you take away the latter as well. This means that if the state takes the right to own a property as its own, then it also takes those other rights for itself. Pope Pius XI saw this tyrannical, anti-family system very clearly:

 

(T)here is a country where the children are actually being torn from the bosom of the family, to be formed (or, to speak more accurately, to be deformed and depraved) in godless schools and associations, to irreligion and hatred, according to the theories of advanced socialism; and thus is renewed in a real and more terrible manner the slaughter of the Innocents.[37]

 

          A socialist-leaning state (even if not full-blown socialist) will assume for itself the duties that are supposed to be the parents’. And parents are justified in reacting against such an injustice and lack of respect toward parental duties. Content creator and commentator Raffy Zamora’s reaction to the push for the so-called Comprehensive Sexuality Education (CSE) bill here in the Philippines is the right reaction to have if you’re a parent: “As a father, I will not stand by and watch my children’s future be shaped by forces that undermine everything we believe in.”[38] The right to educate children – especially in the most intimate of topics, sexuality – does not belong to the state, but to those who love and care for these children the most: mom and dad. More than modules and PowerPoint presentations, the children need proximate and personal love, care, and respect of human dignity that no teacher at school can ever provide.

 

          Socialism’s violation of family rights is just a specified way of saying that it goes against the principle of subsidiarity. The Catechism of the Catholic Church defines subsidiarity as the principle which says that “a community of a higher order should not interfere in the internal life of a community of a lower order, depriving the latter of its functions, but rather should support it in case of need and help to co-ordinate its activity with the activities of the rest of society, always with a view to the common good.”[39] In other words, “the community must not deprive individuals, nor larger communities deprive smaller communities, of the opportunity to do what they can for themselves.”[40]

 

           Subsidiarity is the aspect of Catholic Social teaching against external coercion by any large(r) community against the family and/or any intermediate, non-government groups, in order for people and their immediate connections to freely choose what’s good for them and what satisfies their self-interest. Subsidiarity is the way to oppose tyranny and dictatorship, so that the state does not acquire too much power. as Pope Pius XI wrote: “Just as it is gravely wrong to take from individuals what they can accomplish by their own initiative and industry and give it to the community, so also it is an injustice and at the same time a grave evil and disturbance of right order to assign to a greater and higher association what lesser and subordinate organizations can do”[41] Given their goals, socialism, even those who advocate for what they would call “democratic socialism,” always ends up becoming tyrannical and depriving people of their freedom and rights. Again, history is a witness to this. The only way to fight this collectivist mentality is to strengthen our family units and our local communities through respecting subsidiarity.

 

 

Socialism vs Justice and Personal Initiative

 

          Recall what we have said above that the goal of socialism/communism is “a classless system in which the means of production are owned communally and private property is nonexistent or severely curtailed.”[42] For the socialist, the fact that there are different social classes – the rich, middle class, and poor –  is proof that the current world order is terrible and unfair. For them, a good society is a society without a socio-economic hierarchy. No one should be richer or poorer than the other. This is the communist ideal.

 

          But is this even possible in a free society? Pope Leo XIII writes:

 

It must be first of all recognized that the condition of things inherent in human affairs must be borne with, for it is impossible to reduce civil society to one dead level. Socialists may in that intent do their utmost, but all striving against nature is in vain. There naturally exist among mankind manifold differences of the most important kind; people differ in capacity, skill, health, strength; and unequal fortune is a necessary result of unequal condition [sic]. Such unequality [sic] is far from being disadvantageous either to individuals or to the community. Social and public life can only be maintained by means of various kinds of capacity for business and the playing of many parts; and each man, as a rule, chooses the part which suits his own peculiar domestic condition.[43]

 

          Just as it is natural for man to own private property and choose to raise a family, so also it is natural for man to have different job interests, skills and talents, which then generates diverse – and therefore unequal – outcomes and wages. Wages are just prices for certain jobs. And remember that a price is adjusted depending on whether or not supply is higher than the demand (or vice versa). Is a particular skill harder to acquire and therefore more rare to have? Given that the supply is lower than the demand in this case, then the wages of a man who has that skill will be higher than the one whose skill(s) is more common. A neurosurgeon’s wages are higher than a dishwasher’s, or a school teacher’s wages are lower than LeBron James’, for the same reason. This is a basic demand of justice and fairness. The lesson here is that fairness doesn’t necessarily mean equal. The two concepts are not synonyms. This “fair inequality” is inevitable in a free society. If I choose to be a security guard at a mall, and you become a member of a successful boy band, then my wages will necessarily be lower than yours. Once again, this is simply the law of supply and demand. In the case of the latter, the supply is lower than the demand. There are only a few successful bands, but they have a lot of fans worldwide. Again: “it is impossible to reduce civil society to one dead level.”

 

          And how are we going to pull off a system without a socio-economic hierarchy anyway? Are we going to force all people to have the same job? Then we will no longer be free in choosing the jobs we like due to state coercion. Are we going to allow the state(s) to mandate that the rich – whether rich individuals or wealthy nations –  postpone their economic progress until poor people and countries catch up? The problem with this is that the very first to suffer are the people that the socialist claims are those that socialists fight for: the poor and the workers. There will be no advances in things like medical technology since the most financially capable of us – the rich – will be hindered to innovate (again, this is the incentive problem), an innovation that could’ve helped the poor and be more and more affordable once mass production happens. Unemployment will also happen, since those who give jobs do not grow in wealth, which means the said wealth will inevitably be consumed, to the point where companies/employers can no longer afford workers.[44]

 

          How about allowing the state to confiscate an x amount of wealth from the richest and redistribute it to the poor? Besides (once again) the incentive problem (“Why would I wanna earn an x amount or beyond if the state will confiscate it once I reach that amount? I might as well get less profitable jobs.”), think about this: “Where would people work once all the wealth of the richest 1 percent was redistributed?”[45] We have to take note of this very carefully: The real wealth of these rich people are not their mansions and cars, but rather their investments and businesses.

 

(W)e tend to lose sight of the fact that most of the wealth (of the 1 percent) of the wealthiest is invested. It is put to work in the businesses they own and manage, and in stocks and other financial vehicles that provide the capital for countless other businesses. These are the businesses that provide the 99 percent with the goods, services, and employment that they regularly enjoy and often take for granted.

 

Whether it’s a big automotive plant or a small bakery… all businesses that produce goods and employment are owned by someone. It’s businesses that make up most of the wealth of the 1 percent. Confiscating that wealth and giving it to the other 99 percent would mean shifting much of that wealth from investment and production to consumption, since the poor and middle class consume a far higher percentage of their income than the wealthy do. This sudden shift from investment and production to consumption would demolish the infrastructures that makes [sic] jobs, goods, and services possible.[46]

 

The wealth that could’ve grown through investments or businesses and could’ve led to more employment and economic growth through increased profit will most probably be only consumed by the less wealthy, since they are more needy than the richest of us. And even if they invest it and use it to develop and grow their own businesses, the socio-economic hierarchy will not disappear at all; you’ll just put new people in the top 1 percent and new people in the other 99 percent.

 

Are there bad wealthy people, businessmen, and employers that have a tendency to abuse their power against the less wealthy? Sure, but that doesn’t justify the abolishing of the free market and the institution of a more centralized, egalitarian economy. Besides generating more problems, as we’ve seen above, it also blames the system – which, in and of itself, is just a tool – when in fact we should blame and hold the people who abuse the system accountable. Saying that the free market should be banned because it can give rise to abusive actors in the market is like saying we should ban knives because people can use it to kill, or saying we should stop living in a democracy because election fraud and vote buying can happen. In all of these cases, you’ve generated solutions worse than the problems.

 

Conclusion: Socialism vs Human Nature

 

            In this blogpost, I have given reasons why Pope Leo XIII’s criticisms of Socialism in Rerum Novarum are justified. Notice, however, that at the very heart of his criticisms, it’s not because he sees socialism as just a poor economic method or an impractical system that could’ve worked if we were living in a different historical era. Rather, he sees the problem as essentially an anthropological issue. Socialism, before it is an economic system or a sociological theory, is a claim about human nature. Socialism claims that the human person is basically reduced to his collective role, forgetting that he also has the right and capability for personal initiative as an individual and a human person in himself. Socialism denies a fundamental truth that man can take care of himself and his family through private property and through diverse means of earning wages in an autonomous fashion, distinct from the state. As St. John Paul II wrote in Centesimus Annus:

 

Marxism criticized capitalist bourgeois societies, blaming them for the commercialization and alienation of human existence. This rebuke is of course based on a mistaken and inadequate idea of alienation, derived solely from the sphere of relationships of production and ownership, that is, giving them a materialistic foundation and moreover denying the legitimacy and positive value of market relationships even in their own sphere. Marxism thus ends up by affirming that only in a collective society can alienation be eliminated. However, the historical experience of socialist countries has sadly demonstrated that collectivism does not do away with alienation but rather increases it, adding to it a lack of basic necessities and economic inefficiency.[47]

 

          Together with Pope Leo XIII, St. John Paul II rightly concludes:

 

(T)he fundamental error of socialism is anthropological in nature. Socialism considers the individual person simply as an element, a molecule within the social organism, so that the good of the individual is completely subordinated to the functioning of the socio-economic mechanism. Socialism likewise maintains that the good of the individual can be realized without reference to his free choice, to the unique and exclusive responsibility which he exercises in the face of good or evil. Man is thus reduced to a series of social relationships, and the concept of the person as the autonomous subject of moral decision disappears, the very subject whose decisions build the social order. From this mistaken conception of the person there arise both a distortion of law, which defines the sphere of the exercise of freedom, and an opposition to private property. A person who is deprived of something he can call "his own", and of the possibility of earning a living through his own initiative, comes to depend on the social machine and on those who control it. This makes it much more difficult for him to recognize his dignity as a person, and hinders progress towards the building up of an authentic human community.[48]

 

“All striving against nature is in vain.If our arguments above do not prove this, all we do is look at the societies that adopted socialism and all the deaths and human rights violations that happened within them. We’ve already mentioned the 5 million who died due to famine during Stalin’s reign. There were also the 30 million that died at the hands of Mao Zedong due to his prohibition of owning private farms,[49] the lack of electricity and unpaved roads in North Korea,[50] and execution of more than 10,000 after Fidel Castro’s 1959 revolution in Cuba.[51] That’s not even exhaustive. According to The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression,[52] the number of deaths due to communism worldwide is more than 94 million. If that's not proof that socialism is against humanity, what is?

 

Let us therefore resist this error which is still subscribed to even by many people today, like the Communist Party of the Philippines.[53] Let us not be afraid to expose its evil ways. Let us, like Pope Francis, not hesitate to proclaim: “The Marxist ideology is wrong."



[1] Mering, N. (2021). Awake, not Woke: A Christian Response to the Cult of Progressive Ideology. TAN Books. 28-31.

 

[2] Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. Manifesto of the Communist Party (1848). Marxists.org Publications. (n.d.). https://www.marxists.org/admin/books/manifesto/

 

[3] Manifesto of the Communist Party. Chapter II. emphasis added.

 

[4] Horn, T., & Pakaluk, C. R. (2020). Can a Catholic be a Socialist?: The Answer is No - Here’s Why. 22-24

 

[5] Admin. (2021, October 29). Program for a People’s Democratic Revolution. PRWC | Philippine Revolution Web Central. https://www.cpp.ph/2018/06/30/program-for-a-peoples-democratic-revolution/

 

[6] End private property, not Kenny Loggins. (2016, February 13). https://jacobin.com/2016/02/socialism-marxism-private-property-person-lennon-imagine-kenny-loggins. emphasis added.

 

[7]  Program for a People’s Democratic Revolution. emphasis added.

 

[8] The word “basic” is an important qualifier/adjective for a proper definition. It’s not as if the government is not involved in regulating a non-socialist economy (unless you’re someone like an anarcho-capitalist), but rather that the government is in control of how basic goods (like food which is a basic need) are distributed or produced in socialism. It is therefore a question of how, not if, a government is involved. See Socialism versus the Family. (n.d.). http://www.edwardfeser.com/unpublishedpapers/socialismvsthefamily.html

 

[9] Socialism versus the Family. emphasis in the original

 

[10] Can a Catholic be a Socialist? 83-85, 97-99

[11] Ibid. 21-22

 

[12] Zieba, M. (2023). Papal Economics: The Catholic Church on Democratic Capitalism, from Rerum Novarum to Caritas in Veritate. Intercollegiate Studies Institute. 7.

 

[13] Rerum Novarum (May 15, 1891) | LEO XIII. (1891, May 14). https://www.vatican.va/content/leo-xiii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_l-xiii_enc_15051891_rerum-novarum.html

 

[14] Rerum Novarum; 1, 3

 

[15]  Rerum Novarum; 4

[16] Ibid.

 

[17] Socialism versus the Family. emphasis added.

[18] Rerum Novarum; 7

[19] Ibid., 6, 7

 

[20] Sirico, R. (2012). Defending the Free Market: The Moral Case for a Free Economy. Regenery Publishing. 125-126

 

[21] Can a Catholic be a Socialist? 32

 

[22] Ibid., 81. emphasis in the original

[23] Ibid., 83

 

[24] Ibid., 83-84

 

[25] Defending the Free Market. 35

[26] Can a Catholic be a Socialist? 19-20

 

[27] Defending the Free Market. 36

 

[28] Rerum Novarum; 5. emphases added

[29]  Rerum Novarum; 12. emphasis added.

 

[30] Ibid., 13

[31] Ibid., 13. emphases added.

[32]  Ibid., 14. emphases added.

[33] Defending the Free Market. 33

[34] Manifesto of the Communist Party. Chapter II.

 

[35] What is Socialism? – World Socialist Movement. (n.d.). https://www.worldsocialism.org/wsm/a-homepage-section/introductory-material/what-is-socialism/

[36] Socialism versus the Family. emphasis added.

 

[37] Divini Illius Magistri (December 31, 1929) | PIUS XI. (1929, December 30). https://www.vatican.va/content/pius-xi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_enc_31121929_divini-illius-magistri.html

 

[38] Peanut Gallery Media Network. (2025, January 26). Here are the details of the UNBELIEVABLE bill authored by Senator Risa Hontiveros | Ep 29 [Video]. YouTube. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=52ijvj95eC0

 

[39] uCatholic. (2012, July 22). Catechism of the Catholic Church #1883. uCatholic. https://ucatholic.com/catechism/1883/

 

[40] Papal Economics. 10.

 

[42] Chen, J. (2024, July 1). What is Communism? Definition and History. Investopedia. https://www.investopedia.com/terms/c/communism.asp

 

[43] Rerum Novarum; 17. emphases added.

[44]  Defending the Free Market. xviii.

[45] Defending the Free Market. 102.

 

[46] Ibid.

[47] Centesimus Annus (1 May 1991) | John Paul II. (1991, May 1). https://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_01051991_centesimus-annus.html. 41. emphasis added

 

[48] Ibid., 13. emphases added.

 

[49] Can a Catholic be a Socialist? 98

 

[50] Ibid., 100

[51] Ibid., 102

 

[52] Courtois, S., Werth, N., Panné, J.-L., Paczkowski, A., Bartosek, K., & Margolin, J.-L. (1999). The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression. Harvard University Press.

 

[53] Philippine Revolution Web Central. (n.d.). PRWC | Philippine Revolution Web Central. PRWC | Philippine Revolution Web Central. https://www.cpp.ph/

 Thought experiment: Imagine you’re in middle-to-late 19th-century England. New opportunities arise for you, as an able-bodied adult, when it comes to making money. Instead of remaining in your rural village to farm, you decided to give the factory a shot. But once you step into the city, problems with this new industrial system immediately make themselves evident: harsh working conditions, inhumane treatment of workers, unreasonably low wages, and even child labor. You know you want such a system to change. Deep inside, it is obvious that there are blatant violations of man’s rights in such circumstances. The question is: What is the right solution?

 

          This is the historical situation that moved Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels to publish in 1848 The Communist Manifesto. With Marx’s hegelian-inspired, materialistic view of history as one big class struggle between the ruling class/bourgeoisie and the working class/proletariat as theoretical backdrop,[1] the two saw that the best means toward renewing society’s mistreatment of workers is nothing less than a revolution: “Let the ruling classes tremble at a Communistic revolution. The proletarians (poor workers) have nothing to lose but their chains. They have a world to win.”[2]

 

What is Socialism?

 

But if revolution is the means, what is communism’s end? Marx couldn’t be more clear: “the theory of the Communists may be summed up in the single sentence: abolition of private property.”[3] In other words, for communism, the solution to the so-called tyrannical control of industry by the ruling class is to strip them of the private ownership of the means of production of goods and services so that they’d be communally owned.[4] The Communist Party of the Philippines, in their official constitution and program, is also very explicit about this goal: “The private ownership of the means of production and distribution by the big bourgeoisie and landlord class must be abolished.”[5] This is so that there’d be no hierarchy of social classes, but only a classless society, a society which, in the mind of the communists, would be promoting equality and fairness to its citizens.

 

This politico-economic theory, which advocates for “taking away the source of capitalists’ power (which is) the private ownership of property,”[6] is otherwise known as socialism. To once again quote the Communist Party of the Philippines, this is a socio-political vision in which “(p)ublic ownership of the means of production shall become dominant and state economic planning will direct the development of a well-balanced socialist economy… After the socialist transformation of industry and the entire economy, the Party shall ensure that there is no retrogression into private ownership of the means of production.[7] More precisely defined, socialism “concerns government ownership and control over basic[8] means for the production and distribution of goods.”[9]

 

“Hold on a minute,” you might ask, “I thought socialism advocates for the social/communal ownership of the sources of goods and services; why is it now defined as government/state ownership of the same?” It’s simple, really: If, for instance, the agricultural industry is to be owned by all (as was the aspirations of socialist rulers like Stalin and Mao)[10] so that all can be provided for, someone has to be in charge to regulate it and see its proper distribution, which is none other than the state. So, at the end of the day, communal ownership isn’t really communal in the strict sense when it comes to socialism. It’s more of a state control of a nation's economic sector; we can thus call a socialist economy a command/planned economy.[11]

 

Now that we have properly defined what socialism is, we now have to ask: Is this the right solution to the socio-economic ills not only during Marx’s time, but ours as well?

 

Here Comes the Lion

 

            The social conditions in which Marx formulated his communist-socialist vision are also the same contexts that Pope Leo XIII (d. 1903) wished to address in what is now considered the “first social encyclical,”[12] Rerum Novarum[13] (English translation: “new things”), published on May 15, 1891. Just like Marx, Pope Leo saw many problems in the “new things” of the industrial revolution, particularly regarding the circumstances in which workers find themselves. Among other things, he saw “the utter poverty of the masses,” “moral degeneracy,” “rapacious usury,” and the “misery and wretchedness pressing so unjustly on the majority of the working class.”[14]

 

But the similarities between the two end there. Marx and Leo may have diagnosed the same disease, but they have provided cures that can’t be more different. As a matter of fact, the latter even went so far as to say that the socialist solution to the industrial problem, which is “to do away with property,”[15] is a cure worse than the disease: “their (i.e. the socialists) contentions are so clearly powerless to end the controversy that were they carried into effect the working man himself would be among the first to suffer. They are, moreover, emphatically unjust, for they would rob the lawful possessor, distort the functions of the State, and create utter confusion in the community.”[16]

 

So, Pope Leo XIII is explicit: socialism is a terrible solution to the problem. Why did he think so? His position can be summed up into three reasons: Socialism is wrong because (1) it goes against the natural right to private property, (2) it violates the principle of subsidiarity and the rights of the family, and (3) it restricts personal freedom of initiative to take on diverse interests and jobs, which will generate diverse and unequal outcomes and wages.

 

Let’s take a look at these two reasons and why, in my estimation, these reasons make a good case against socialism.

 

Socialism vs Private Property

 

We’ve already seen that socialism is against the private ownership of property. For the sake of precision, however, it would be helpful if we can define exactly what it means to own something. The philosopher Edward Feser provides a helpful definition of ownership:

 

(T)o own something is essentially to possess a bundle of rights over the thing.  For example, suppose I own a certain pencil.What that involves is my having the right to use the pencil whenever I want to, the right to lend it to others if I so desire, the right not to lend it to them if that’s what I prefer, the right to chew on it if I feel anxious, the right to break it in half if I want to shorten it or simply as a way to take out frustration, and so forth.To own the pencil is to have a bundle of such rights, and to have such a bundle of rights over the pencil is to own it.[17]

 

          So, to own something is to have a right to be able to dispose of it in an autonomous fashion. Of course, you have the obvious moral and legal limits to such an autonomous use/disuse, but overall, this sounds like a very intuitive definition that all of us can agree upon. If I own something, I can do with it whatever I like (within moral and legal limits, of course).

 

          Common sense also tells us that the right to own private property is a natural right, or a right that springs forth from us simply by being human, not by some deliberate contractual obligation or state imposition. Leo XIII says that, when it comes to said right:

 

There is no need to bring in the State. Man precedes the State, and possesses, prior to the formation of any State, the right of providing for the substance of his body.[18]

 

          I have the natural right to own food/ingredients that can help me cook food, because I have the right to feed myself for the sake of self-preservation. And this right was not arbitrarily given to me. It’s simply a consequence of my being human. Take note, I have a natural right to own, not just access, goods that I will need to preserve myself. Access to goods is all an animal needs to have. If an elephant is thirsty, all he needs to do is drink from a lake. But unlike animals, humans have intellects, which not only tells us what we need at the present but allows us to discern and prepare for the future. The conclusion is obvious: We must therefore not just have goods for today or at this moment; we must also keep and safeguard things (and the source for such things) for future use, which is just another way to say we have the right to own private property.

 

It is the mind, or reason, which is the predominant element in us who are human creatures; it is this which renders a human being human, and distinguishes him essentially from the brute. And on this very account - that man alone among the animal creation is endowed with reason - it must be within his right to possess things not merely for temporary and momentary use, as other living things do, but to have and to hold them in stable and permanent possession; he must have not only things that perish in the use, but those also which, though they have been reduced into use, continue for further use in after time…

 

For man, fathoming by his faculty of reason matters without number, linking the future with the present, and being master of his own acts, guides his ways under the eternal law and the power of God, whose providence governs all things. Wherefore, it is in his power to exercise his choice not only as to matters that regard his present welfare, but also about those which he deems may be for his advantage in time yet to come. Hence, man not only should possess the fruits of the earth, but also the very soil, inasmuch as from the produce of the earth he has to lay by provision for the future.[19]

 

          The consequence of such reasoning is also obvious: If ownership of private property is a natural right, then the socialist aspiration to abolish it is a violation of a natural right, and hence must be condemned.

 

          What would happen if we abolished private property and opted instead for a system where property of goods and services are socially/communally owned and excessively regulated by the state? Simply put: the consequences would be disastrous.

 

          First, such a system will succumb to what economist Friedrich Hayek called the “synoptic delusion” or “the knowledge problem.” Fr. Robert Sirico describes it this way:

 

The synoptic (one-eyed) delusion is the notion that a single analyst – not necessarily a single individual, but a single entity or agency – can accurately comprehend and assess the entire range of information necessary to predictably manipulate a complex social organism such as a modern culture or economy.[20]

 

In other words, a single person/body of persons cannot know the exact ways to navigate economic matters, like pricing, for knowledge in such matters are dispersed through every single individual, since they are the ones who know their wants and needs, and not a single individual or group. But this is exactly the problem of socialism: Socialists want economic knowledge to be centralized/isolated in a single system, which is impossible. For example, how will we know if there’s a shortage in the production of bread given, say, a lack of resources to make it? In a free market system, such knowledge could be communicated to all by the setting of prices: those who produce flour and eggs that can make bread will increase the prices for said produces in order to properly manage the scarce resources by regulating customer consumption and so that the producers can have more funds/incentives to produce more of it. On the other hand, if there’s an abundance of said ingredients, then these same producers will lower the prices to incentivize consumers to buy more of it and to discourage producers from making too much of something that is not too profitable.[21]

 

And herein lies the socialist problem: Without multiple producers and consumers who represent the wants, needs, and resources of the collective through privately owned businesses and enterprises, only the state can arbitrarily set prices and/or produce (or not produce) goods, which will inevitably fail to reflect the law of supply and demand among the people, which would then lead to the overproduction of supplies that have little to no demand and underproduction of supplies that have so much demand. This is because such a society will have statesmen relying on guess work in terms of production instead of the more reliable price system that free societies have and which we have explained above.

 

This is exactly what happened in the USSR. As Trent Horn and Dr. Catherine Pakaluk noted: “(U)nlike capitalist economies that allow prices (and production) to adjust according to consumer choice, the Soviet system set rigid production targets, and consumers just had to ‘choose’ whatever was offered to them.”[22] In other words, because the Soviet Union relied on production quotas instead of prices, the people had no choice but to take what was produced, instead of what they really wanted or needed. The negative effects of this were felt during the reign of Joseph Stalin who, because he wanted to prioritize national defense, “focused on heavy industry at the expense of things like food production.”[23] Because he arbitrarily chose to produce more with regards steel and the like instead of food (not to mention his forced confiscation of Ukrainian farms for the sake of his “project”), this led to people (who’d naturally prefer food over steel) starving to death. This famine, which lasted from 1932-1933, killed 5 million.[24] This is the effect of not letting the people themselves decide what they need to own and buy to preserve themselves and presuming that only one person or party can determine that for everyone. A lot of evil things can indeed happen if you violate a natural right.

 

But besides the knowledge problem, socialism’s desire of centralizing instead of freeing the economy at the hands of the people also creates what can be called “the incentive problem” or what I prefer to call “the public bathroom problem.” To explain what this is, it would be helpful to cite an example from history.

 

In the year 1620, the so-called Plymouth Colony, one of the first few English colonies in America, decided to grow their food communally and distributed it equally to all who belong to their colony, including those who didn’t work for the growth of the foods. For someone sympathetic to socialist principles, this sounds like paradise. But nothing could be further from the truth: “The result was economic chaos, disease, starvation, death, and the near extinction of the first New England settlers.”[25] How did this happen?

 

Think about it: If I, who works hard in the communal farm, will get the same amount of food as the one who works less than me or is too lazy to work for the community, then why would I bother working hard, not to mention working at all? Also, the complaint of the young men in the colony was: Why would I work for the sustenance of someone else’s wife and children if those aren’t my family? Why can’t the husband and father of that same family work for themselves?[26]

 

The result was that the workers lost the incentive to work because the lazy man got the same ration of food as the hardworking man anyway. But if no one’s working or at least starts working less than before, then this will lead to decreased production, which will lead to inevitable death by starvation the less incentives there are to work and the less productions of food occur.

 

How did the colony solve this problem? It’s simple: the people were allowed to own portions of the land and let them work for their own sustenance. “The result was the first plentiful harvest and the first bountiful thanksgiving.”[27]

 

This is, once again, common sense. People work to get paid for the sake of self-preservation. And this is not selfishness, this is natural self-interest, which everyone has: You eat and drink for yourself; it follows that you will also work for food and drink for yourself. If we can get these goods for free every time, no one will work. Getting paid fairly and being able to procure goods through the wage is a natural incentive for working. As Pope Leo XIII said:

 

It is surely undeniable that, when a man engages in remunerative labor, the impelling reason and motive of his work is to obtain property, and thereafter to hold it as his very own. If one man hires out to another his strength or skill, he does so for the purpose of receiving in return what is necessary for the satisfaction of his needs; he therefore expressly intends to acquire a right full and real, not only to the remuneration, but also to the disposal of such remuneration, just as he pleases… Socialists, therefore, by endeavoring to transfer the possessions of individuals to the community at large, strike at the interests of every wage-earner, since they would deprive him of the liberty of disposing of his wages, and thereby of all hope and possibility of increasing his resources and of bettering his condition in life.[28]

 

No one would bother working if, in the name of “equality” and “community,” I can get the same amount of goods as the one who doesn’t work by a deliberate choice. And because no one would find it reasonable to work, the result will be production decrease, as noted above, and the ruin of society will be inevitable, as in what happened in the Plymouth Colony.

 

This is why I also call this “the public bathroom problem.” There’s a reason why public bathrooms are generally dirtier and nastier than our bathrooms at home: There’s not much incentive to clean the former, because someone else can clean it for me (i.e. janitors and other good-willed people), with the result being that most of the time it isn’t even cleaned well or not cleaned at all. On the other hand, we prefer to clean the latter because it belongs to us. Same thing with property ownership and access to goods: If I can work to own it for the sake of my own survival, then great. But if it can be guaranteed that I can have access to these goods without even working (because someone else will work on my behalf), then I’d rather not work, with the inevitable result being that no one will (want to) work, unless, of course, the state forces us to work, which leads to the problem of tyranny, the major issue of all socialist states throughout history – from Russia to North Korea.

 

Socialism vs The Family (and Subsidiarity)

 

            As noted above, man “precedes the state” and thus has natural rights, like the right to private property, “prior to the formation of any State.”          But these natural rights flow from man’s natural dispositions. Look again at the right to private property. Man has a right to private property because, by nature, he is disposed to plan his life ahead of time and thus has to have ownership of goods in accordance with this plan. But besides our rational disposition or ability to plan our lives, we also have the disposition not just to preserve ourselves but our species, which can be done through the raising of a family, enabled through the procreation between persons who differ in sex: Man and woman. Humans, who have a disposition to procreate and preserve the human species, thus have a natural right to marry and have children, a right that is also independent of the state:

 

The rights here spoken of, belonging to each individual man, are seen in much stronger light when considered in relation to man's social and domestic obligations. In choosing a state of life, it is indisputable that all are at full liberty to follow the counsel of Jesus Christ as to observing virginity, or to bind themselves by the marriage tie. No human law can abolish the natural and original right of marriage, nor in any way limit the chief and principal purpose of marriage ordained by God's authority from the beginning: "Increase and multiply."(3) Hence we have the family, the "society" of a man's house - a society very small, one must admit, but none the less [sic] a true society, and one older than any State. Consequently, it has rights and duties peculiar to itself which are quite independent of the State.[29]

 

          The consequence of this natural right, Pope Leo XIII said, also affects the right to private property. Here’s a helpful way of thinking about it: If X has a right toward Y, then Y has a duty toward X. An analogy might be helpful: just as a statesman has a duty toward the nation, like safeguarding the public peace, this means that it goes hand in hand with the nation’s right to have its peace maintained. If a student has a right to be educated, then a teacher has a duty to educate. I hope it’s clear: My duty to do something to others implies the rights of the others to be served by me. Rights and duties, in other words, are relational realities. It makes sense through a reference to another person.

 

          Now, when it comes to the family, the person (Pope Leo specifies the father)[30] who freely enters married/family life obviously has the duty to provide for his family. But remember: duties are accompanied by rights. So if the father has the duty to provide for his family, then he has the right to be able to keep for himself the goods (or the sources of such goods) that will allow him to fulfill this duty – like a house or food supply accessed and bought through just wages. We can see here that the right to private property is “extended,” so to speak, to one’s familial duties so that one not only has the right to own for oneself, but also for those he’s responsible towards.

 

That right to property, therefore, which has been proved to belong naturally to individual persons, must in like wise [sic] belong to a man in his capacity of head of a family; nay, that right is all the stronger in proportion as the human person receives a wider extension in the family group. It is a most sacred law of nature that a father should provide food and all necessaries for those whom he has begotten; and, similarly, it is natural that he should wish that his children, who carry on, so to speak, and continue his personality, should be by him provided with all that is needful to enable them to keep themselves decently from want and misery amid the uncertainties of this mortal life. Now, in no other way can a father effect this except by the ownership of productive property, which he can transmit to his children by inheritance. A family, no less than a State, is, as We have said, a true society, governed by an authority peculiar to itself, that is to say, by the authority of the father. Provided, therefore, the limits which are prescribed by the very purposes for which it exists be not transgressed, the family has at least equal rights with the State in the choice and pursuit of the things needful to its preservation and its just liberty. We say, "at least equal rights"; for, inasmuch as the domestic household is antecedent, as well in idea as in fact, to the gathering of men into a community, the family must necessarily have rights and duties which are prior to those of the community, and founded more immediately in nature. If the citizens, if the families on entering into association and fellowship, were to experience hindrance in a commonwealth instead of help, and were to find their rights attacked instead of being upheld, society would rightly be an object of detestation rather than of desire.[31]

 

          Just as taking away the ownership of an individual in the name of collectivism is a violation of a natural right as we saw above, then it is also a violation of a natural right for other groups/societies “above” the family to take away this parental responsibility and make it their own. Leo XIII formulates this obvious conclusion:

 

The contention, then, that the civil government should at its option intrude into and exercise intimate control over the family and the household is a great and pernicious error. True, if a family finds itself in exceeding distress, utterly deprived of the counsel of friends, and without any prospect of extricating itself, it is right that extreme necessity be met by public aid, since each family is a part of the commonwealth. In like manner, if within the precincts of the household there occur grave disturbance of mutual rights, public authority should intervene to force each party to yield to the other its proper due; for this is not to deprive citizens of their rights, but justly and properly to safeguard and strengthen them. But the rulers of the commonwealth must go no further; here, nature bids them stop. Paternal authority can be neither abolished nor absorbed by the State; for it has the same source as human life itself. "The child belongs to the father," and is, as it were, the continuation of the father's personality; and speaking strictly, the child takes its place in civil society, not of its own right, but in its quality as member of the family in which it is born. And for the very reason that "the child belongs to the father" it is, as St. Thomas Aquinas says, "before it attains the use of free will, under the power and the charge of its parents." The socialists, therefore, in setting aside the parent and setting up a State supervision, act against natural justice, and destroy the structure of the home.[32]

 

If it isn’t obvious yet why this is such a big deal, allow me to explain further. Fr. Sirico argues that private property is such an important right that, when we take it away, we take away other rights that depend on it. He puts it this way:

 

If you are to have a right to free speech, but are not permitted to publish a book at a private publisher, or to own a newspaper or TV or radio station, or (increasingly) even to post an opinion online because the government has begun to treat the internet as if it owns it, then in what practical sense can you be said to have the right to free speech?

 

The same is true of religion. If the state strips away our economic freedom to decide how and where we use our private means to compensate doctors, nurses, and physical therapists in exchange for medical care, if the government comes to control all of this as if these medical skills and private exchanges were somehow the government’s property, then it suddenly becomes easier for the government to infringe upon one’s right to religious freedom in certain important ways… (like) the Obama Administration’s Department of Health and Human Services in early 2012, requiring religious institutions to provide abortifacient drugs, sterilization, and contraception coverage as part of their health insurance programs even if those religious groups are morally opposed to doing so.[33]

 

            In other words, if you take away private property, you take away man’s initiative in making his quality of life better in a way that would correspond to other natural rights, like free speech and religious liberty. The right to ownership is so fundamental that, if you abolish it, you abolish many other rights together with it, uprooting a tree so that it bears fruit no more.

 

          Let me give another example. If the state takes away a husband and father’s right to dispose of his wages in the best way possible – like the right to use it for his children’s tuition or to buy books or school materials – then the state not only took away his right to private property, it also took away his right to educate his children or choose the best possible education system his children needs. This is the “great and pernicious error” that Leo XIII condemns.

 

          This would also give rise to the problems mentioned in the previous section, like the knowledge problem. As I would like to say: The man from Malacañang does not lose sleep regarding whether or not I’ve already eaten dinner. That concern is for the parents and closest relatives/friends only. Also, what if my problem is not lack of food, but lack of self control in consuming food? The people from the highest of offices won’t know that. If they take the role of parents instead of my actual parents, then if they misjudge that the people in my home need more food supply, that will be to my health’s detriment. My family would’ve known that what I needed was to spend money on diet products and gym membership.

 

          This is why Marx and Engels saw the family as a threat to their collectivist mentality. Just like their disdain for private property, they were very clear that abolishing the family is part and parcel with their desire for a communal ownership of goods: “Abolition of the family! Even the most radical flare up at this infamous proposal of the Communists.”[34] The connection is clear: Any good parent will want to shield his family from outside forces that (at least in his judgment) can corrupt his children’s moral formation and is more inclined to help his family before the larger community (this is also common sense: we know there’s a huge difference, morally speaking, between a man who fails to feed his next-door neighbor and a man who fails to feed his own children; the latter is more morally depraved). But at the heart of the communist-socialist ideal is that these so-called “outside forces” and “larger community” are the priority over any smaller group such as the family (see the definition of “socialism” above), because “(c)entral to the meaning of socialism is common ownership. This means the resources of the world being owned in common by the entire global population.”[35] Therefore, if the family hinders the progress of the collective, we have to sacrifice and abolish it.

 

          This is why the push for a stronger and more centralized government will inevitably weaken the family unit, while a stronger family unit is a form of resistance to such efforts. You can only fight for one or the other. You cannot have both. Feser states:

 

(T)he more the traditional family structure breaks down, the more individuals there are – especially single mothers and children – who find themselves without sufficient private means of support, and thus require greater governmental assistance.  This plausibly accounts for what social scientists have called the “marriage gap” in U.S. voting patterns. Both married men and married women are likelier [sic] to vote for conservative candidates.  By contrast, unmarried men are significantly more likely to vote for liberal candidates, and unmarried women are massively more likely to vote for liberal candidates.  If you are a breadwinner capable of supporting a family or the spouse of such a breadwinner, you are less likely to need state assistance and are bound to resent the government taxing away income that could be used for the benefit of your family.  By contrast, if you do not have a family to support you will be less resentful of taxation, and you are single mother with children or a woman unable to find a husband you are bound to regard government as a kind of surrogate provider.[36]

 

          Remember that many other rights (like the right to educate one’s children) presuppose private property such that if you take away the former, you take away the latter as well. This means that if the state takes the right to own a property as its own, then it also takes those other rights for itself. Pope Pius XI saw this tyrannical, anti-family system very clearly:

 

(T)here is a country where the children are actually being torn from the bosom of the family, to be formed (or, to speak more accurately, to be deformed and depraved) in godless schools and associations, to irreligion and hatred, according to the theories of advanced socialism; and thus is renewed in a real and more terrible manner the slaughter of the Innocents.[37]

 

          A socialist-leaning state (even if not full-blown socialist) will assume for itself the duties that are supposed to be the parents’. And parents are justified in reacting against such an injustice and lack of respect toward parental duties. Content creator and commentator Raffy Zamora’s reaction to the push for the so-called Comprehensive Sexuality Education (CSE) bill here in the Philippines is the right reaction to have if you’re a parent: “As a father, I will not stand by and watch my children’s future be shaped by forces that undermine everything we believe in.”[38] The right to educate children – especially in the most intimate of topics, sexuality – does not belong to the state, but to those who love and care for these children the most: mom and dad. More than modules and PowerPoint presentations, the children need proximate and personal love, care, and respect of human dignity that no teacher at school can ever provide.

 

          Socialism’s violation of family rights is just a specified way of saying that it goes against the principle of subsidiarity. The Catechism of the Catholic Church defines subsidiarity as the principle which says that “a community of a higher order should not interfere in the internal life of a community of a lower order, depriving the latter of its functions, but rather should support it in case of need and help to co-ordinate its activity with the activities of the rest of society, always with a view to the common good.”[39] In other words, “the community must not deprive individuals, nor larger communities deprive smaller communities, of the opportunity to do what they can for themselves.”[40]

 

           Subsidiarity is the aspect of Catholic Social teaching against external coercion by any large(r) community against the family and/or any intermediate, non-government groups, in order for people and their immediate connections to freely choose what’s good for them and what satisfies their self-interest. Subsidiarity is the way to oppose tyranny and dictatorship. as Pope Pius XI wrote: “Just as it is gravely wrong to take from individuals what they can accomplish by their own initiative and industry and give it to the community, so also it is an injustice and at the same time a grave evil and disturbance of right order to assign to a greater and higher association what lesser and subordinate organizations can do”[41] Given their goals, socialism, even those who advocate for what they would call “democratic socialism,” always ends up becoming tyrannical and depriving people of their freedom and rights. Again, history is a witness to this. The only way to fight this collectivist mentality is to strengthen our family units and our local communities through respecting subsidiarity.

 

 

Socialism vs Justice and Personal Initiative

 

          Recall what we have said above that the goal of socialism/communism is “a classless system in which the means of production are owned communally and private property is nonexistent or severely curtailed.”[42] For the socialist, the fact that there are different social classes – the rich, middle class, and poor –  is proof that the current world order is terrible and unfair. For them, a good society is a society without a socio-economic hierarchy. No one should be richer or poorer than the other. This is the communist ideal.

 

          But is this even possible in a free society? Pope Leo XIII writes:

 

It must be first of all recognized that the condition of things inherent in human affairs must be borne with, for it is impossible to reduce civil society to one dead level. Socialists may in that intent do their utmost, but all striving against nature is in vain. There naturally exist among mankind manifold differences of the most important kind; people differ in capacity, skill, health, strength; and unequal fortune is a necessary result of unequal condition [sic]. Such unequality [sic] is far from being disadvantageous either to individuals or to the community. Social and public life can only be maintained by means of various kinds of capacity for business and the playing of many parts; and each man, as a rule, chooses the part which suits his own peculiar domestic condition.[43]

 

          Just as it is natural for man to own private property and choose to raise a family, so also it is natural for man to have different job interests, skills and talents, which then generates diverse – and therefore unequal – outcomes and wages. Wages are just prices for certain jobs. And remember that a price is adjusted depending on whether or not supply is higher than the demand (or vice versa). Is a particular skill harder to acquire and therefore more rare to have? Given that the supply is lower than the demand in this case, then the wages of a man who has that skill will be higher than the one whose skill(s) is more common. A neurosurgeon’s wages are higher than a dishwasher’s, or a school teacher’s wages are lower than LeBron James’, for the same reason. This is a basic demand of justice and fairness. The lesson here is that fairness doesn’t necessarily mean equal. The two concepts are not synonyms. This “fair inequality” is inevitable in a free society. If I choose to be a security guard at a mall, and you become a member of a successful boy band, then my wages will necessarily be lower than yours. Once again, this is simply the law of supply and demand. In the case of the latter, the supply is lower than the demand. There are only a few successful bands, but they have a lot of fans worldwide. Again: “it is impossible to reduce civil society to one dead level.”

 

          And how are we going to pull off a system without a socio-economic hierarchy anyway? Are we going to force all people to have the same job? Then we will no longer be free in choosing the jobs we like due to state coercion. Are we going to allow the state(s) to mandate that the rich – whether rich individuals or wealthy nations –  postpone their economic progress until poor people and countries catch up? The problem with this is that the very first to suffer are the people that the socialist claims are those that socialists fight for: the poor and the workers. There will be no advances in things like medical technology since the most financially capable of us – the rich – will be hindered to innovate (again, this is the incentive problem), an innovation that could’ve helped the poor and be more and more affordable once mass production happens. Unemployment will also happen, since those who give jobs do not grow in wealth, which means the said wealth will inevitably be consumed, to the point where companies/employers can no longer afford workers.[44]

 

          How about allowing the state to confiscate an x amount of wealth from the richest and redistribute it to the poor? Besides (once again) the incentive problem (“Why would I wanna earn an x amount or beyond if the state will confiscate it once I reach that amount? I might as well get less profitable jobs.”), think about this: “Where would people work once all the wealth of the richest 1 percent was redistributed?”[45] We have to take note of this very carefully: The real wealth of these rich people are not their mansions and cars, but rather their investments and businesses.

 

(W)e tend to lose sight of the fact that most of the wealth (of the 1 percent) of the wealthiest is invested. It is put to work in the businesses they own and manage, and in stocks and other financial vehicles that provide the capital for countless other businesses. These are the businesses that provide the 99 percent with the goods, services, and employment that they regularly enjoy and often take for granted.

 

Whether it’s a big automotive plant or a small bakery… all businesses that produce goods and employment are owned by someone. It’s businesses that make up most of the wealth of the 1 percent. Confiscating that wealth and giving it to the other 99 percent would mean shifting much of that wealth from investment and production to consumption, since the poor and middle class consume a far higher percentage of their income than the wealthy do. This sudden shift from investment and production to consumption would demolish the infrastructures that makes [sic] jobs, goods, and services possible.[46]

 

The wealth that could’ve grown through investments or businesses and could’ve led to more employment and economic growth through increased profit will most probably be only consumed by the less wealthy, since they are more needy than the richest of us. And even if they invest it and use it to develop and grow their own businesses, the socio-economic hierarchy will not disappear at all; you’ll just put new people in the top 1 percent and new people in the other 99 percent.

 

Are there bad wealthy people, businessmen, and employers that have a tendency to abuse their power against the less wealthy? Sure, but that doesn’t justify the abolishing of the free market and the institution of a more centralized, egalitarian economy. Besides generating more problems, as we’ve seen above, it also blames the system – which, in and of itself, is just a tool – when in fact we should blame and hold the people who abuse the system accountable. Saying that the free market should be banned because it can give rise to abusive actors in the market is like saying we should ban knives because people can use it to kill, or saying we should stop living in a democracy because election fraud and vote buying can happen. In all of these cases, you’ve generated solutions worse than the problems.

 

Conclusion: Socialism vs Human Nature

 

            In this blogpost, I have given reasons why Pope Leo XIII’s criticisms of Socialism in Rerum Novarum are justified. Notice, however, that at the very heart of his criticisms, it’s not because he sees socialism as just a poor economic method or an impractical system that could’ve worked if we were living in a different historical era. Rather, he sees the problem as essentially an anthropological issue. Socialism, before it is an economic system or a sociological theory, is a claim about human nature. Socialism claims that the human person is basically reduced to his collective role, forgetting that he also has the right and capability for personal initiative as an individual and a human person in himself. Socialism denies a fundamental truth that man can take care of himself and his family through private property and through diverse means of earning wages in an autonomous fashion, distinct from the state. As St. John Paul II writes in Centesimus Annus:

 

Marxism criticized capitalist bourgeois societies, blaming them for the commercialization and alienation of human existence. This rebuke is of course based on a mistaken and inadequate idea of alienation, derived solely from the sphere of relationships of production and ownership, that is, giving them a materialistic foundation and moreover denying the legitimacy and positive value of market relationships even in their own sphere. Marxism thus ends up by affirming that only in a collective society can alienation be eliminated. However, the historical experience of socialist countries has sadly demonstrated that collectivism does not do away with alienation but rather increases it, adding to it a lack of basic necessities and economic inefficiency.[47]

 

          Together with Pope Leo XIII, St. John Paul II rightly concludes:

 

(T)he fundamental error of socialism is anthropological in nature. Socialism considers the individual person simply as an element, a molecule within the social organism, so that the good of the individual is completely subordinated to the functioning of the socio-economic mechanism. Socialism likewise maintains that the good of the individual can be realized without reference to his free choice, to the unique and exclusive responsibility which he exercises in the face of good or evil. Man is thus reduced to a series of social relationships, and the concept of the person as the autonomous subject of moral decision disappears, the very subject whose decisions build the social order. From this mistaken conception of the person there arise both a distortion of law, which defines the sphere of the exercise of freedom, and an opposition to private property. A person who is deprived of something he can call "his own", and of the possibility of earning a living through his own initiative, comes to depend on the social machine and on those who control it. This makes it much more difficult for him to recognize his dignity as a person, and hinders progress towards the building up of an authentic human community.[48]

 

“All striving against nature is in vain.If our arguments above do not prove this, all we do is look at the societies that adopted socialism and all the deaths and human rights violations that happened within them. We’ve already mentioned the 5 million who died due to famine during Stalin’s reign. There were also the 30 million that died at the hands of Mao Zedong due to his prohibition of owning private farms,[49] the lack of electricity and unpaved roads in North Korea,[50] and execution of more than 10,000 after Fidel Castro’s 1959 revolution in Cuba.[51] That’s not even exhaustive. According to The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression,[52] the number of deaths due to communism worldwide is more than 94 million. If that's not proof that socialism is against humanity, what is?

 

Let us therefore resist this error which is still subscribed to even by many people today, like the Communist Party of the Philippines.[53] Let us not be afraid to expose its evil ways. Let us, like Pope Francis, not hesitate to proclaim: The Marxist ideology is wrong.”


[1] Mering, N. (2021). Awake, not Woke: A Christian Response to the Cult of Progressive Ideology. TAN Books. 28-31.

 

[2] Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. Manifesto of the Communist Party (1848). Marxists.org Publications. (n.d.). https://www.marxists.org/admin/books/manifesto/

 

[3] Manifesto of the Communist Party. Chapter II. emphasis added.

 

[4] Horn, T., & Pakaluk, C. R. (2020). Can a Catholic be a Socialist?: The Answer is No - Here’s Why. 22-24

 

[5] Admin. (2021, October 29). Program for a People’s Democratic Revolution. PRWC | Philippine Revolution Web Central. https://www.cpp.ph/2018/06/30/program-for-a-peoples-democratic-revolution/

 

[6] End private property, not Kenny Loggins. (2016, February 13). https://jacobin.com/2016/02/socialism-marxism-private-property-person-lennon-imagine-kenny-loggins. emphasis added.

 

[7]  Program for a People’s Democratic Revolution. emphasis added.

 

[8] The word “basic” is an important qualifier/adjective for a proper definition. It’s not as if the government is not involved in regulating a non-socialist economy (unless you’re someone like an anarcho-capitalist), but rather that the government is in control of how basic goods (like food which is a basic need) are distributed or produced in socialism. It is therefore a question of how, not if, a government is involved. See Socialism versus the Family. (n.d.). http://www.edwardfeser.com/unpublishedpapers/socialismvsthefamily.html

 

[9] Socialism versus the Family. emphasis in the original

 

[10] Can a Catholic be a Socialist? 83-85, 97-99

[11] Ibid. 21-22

 

[12] Zieba, M. (2023). Papal Economics: The Catholic Church on Democratic Capitalism, from Rerum Novarum to Caritas in Veritate. Intercollegiate Studies Institute. 7.

 

[13] Rerum Novarum (May 15, 1891) | LEO XIII. (1891, May 14). https://www.vatican.va/content/leo-xiii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_l-xiii_enc_15051891_rerum-novarum.html

 

[14] Rerum Novarum; 1, 3

 

[15]  Rerum Novarum; 4

[16] Ibid.

 

[17] Socialism versus the Family. emphasis added.

[18] Rerum Novarum; 7

[19] Ibid., 6, 7

 

[20] Sirico, R. (2012). Defending the Free Market: The Moral Case for a Free Economy. Regenery Publishing. 125-126

 

[21] Can a Catholic be a Socialist? 32

 

[22] Ibid., 81. emphasis in the original

[23] Ibid., 83

 

[24] Ibid., 83-84

 

[25] Defending the Free Market. 35

[26] Can a Catholic be a Socialist? 19-20

 

[27] Defending the Free Market. 36

 

[28] Rerum Novarum; 5. emphases added

[29]  Rerum Novarum; 12. emphasis added.

 

[30] Ibid., 13

[31] Ibid., 13. emphases added.

[32]  Ibid., 14. emphases added.

[33] Defending the Free Market. 33

[34] Manifesto of the Communist Party. Chapter II.

 

[35] What is Socialism? – World Socialist Movement. (n.d.). https://www.worldsocialism.org/wsm/a-homepage-section/introductory-material/what-is-socialism/

[36] Socialism versus the Family. emphasis added.

 

[37] Divini Illius Magistri (December 31, 1929) | PIUS XI. (1929, December 30). https://www.vatican.va/content/pius-xi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_enc_31121929_divini-illius-magistri.html

 

[38] Peanut Gallery Media Network. (2025, January 26). Here are the details of the UNBELIEVABLE bill authored by Senator Risa Hontiveros | Ep 29 [Video]. YouTube. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=52ijvj95eC0

 

[39] uCatholic. (2012, July 22). Catechism of the Catholic Church #1883. uCatholic. https://ucatholic.com/catechism/1883/

 

[40] Papal Economics. 10.

 

[42] Chen, J. (2024, July 1). What is Communism? Definition and History. Investopedia. https://www.investopedia.com/terms/c/communism.asp

 

[43] Rerum Novarum; 17. emphases added.

[44]  Defending the Free Market. xviii.

[45] Defending the Free Market. 102.

 

[46] Ibid.

[47] Centesimus Annus (1 May 1991) | John Paul II. (1991, May 1). https://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_01051991_centesimus-annus.html. 41. emphasis added

 

[48] Ibid., 13. emphases added.

 

[49] Can a Catholic be a Socialist? 98

 

[50] Ibid., 100

[51] Ibid., 102

 

[52] Courtois, S., Werth, N., Panné, J.-L., Paczkowski, A., Bartosek, K., & Margolin, J.-L. (1999). The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression. Harvard University Press.

 

[53] Philippine Revolution Web Central. (n.d.). PRWC | Philippine Revolution Web Central. PRWC | Philippine Revolution Web Central. https://www.cpp.ph/

 

Comments

Popular Posts